Hippocrates Collected Works I

Hippocrates Collected Works I
By Hippocrates
Edited by: W. H. S. Jones (trans.)

Cambridge Harvard University Press 1868


Digital Hippocrates Collection Table of Contents



PREFACE

GENERAL INTRODUCTION
   1. Greek Medicine and Hippocrates
   2. The Hippocratic Collection
   3. Means of Dating Hippocratic Works
   4. Plato's References to Hippocrates
   5. THE COMMENTATORS AND OTHER ANCIENT AUTHORITIES.
   Galen
   6. LIFE OF HIPPOCRATES.
   7. THE ASCLEPIADAE.
   8. THE DOCTRINE OF HUMOURS.
   9. CHIEF DISEASES MENTIONED IN THE HIPPOCRATIC COLLECTION.
   10. πολύς AND ὀλίγος IN THE PLURAL.
   11. THE IONIC DIALECT OF THE HIPPOCRATIC COLLECTION.
   12. MANUSCRIPTS.

ANCIENT MEDICINE
   INTRODUCTION
   ANCIENT MEDICINE
   APPENDIX

AIRS WATERS PLACES
   INTRODUCTION
   MSS. AND EDITIONS.
   AIRS WATERS PLACES

EPIDEMICS I AND III
   INTRODUCTION
   EPIDEMICS I
   EPIDEMICS III: THE CHARACTERS
   EPIDEMICS III
   SIXTEEN CASES

THE OATH
   Introduction
   OATH

PRECEPTS
   INTRODUCTION
   PRECEPTS

NUTRIMENT
   INTRODUCTION
   NUTRIMENT


This electronic edition is funded by the National Library of Medicine History of Medicine Division. This text has been proofread to a high degree of accuracy. It was converted to electronic form using Data Entry.
(Medical Information Disclaimer: It is not the intention of NLM to provide specific medical advice but rather to provide users with information to better understand their health and their diagnosed disorders. Specific medical advice will not be provided, and NLM urges you to consult with a qualified physician for diagnosis and for answers to your personal questions.)

GENERAL INTRODUCTION

3. Means of Dating Hippocratic Works

 [p. xxxii]

of the pulse was unknown to the writers of the chief Hippocratic treatises, we should be more confident in dating, e.g., the work called Nutriment, which recognizes the existence of a pulse. It is a fact that no use is made of this knowledge in any treatise of the collection, but we must not infer from this that the Hippocratic writers were ignorant of pulses. We can only infer that they were ignorant of their medical importance.

(c) The style of a treatise is sometimes a sure test and sometimes not. Sophistic rhetoric is of such a marked character in its most pronounced form that a treatise showing it is not likely to be much earlier than 427 B.C., nor much later than 400 B.C., when sophistic extravagances began to be modified under the influence of the Attic orators. But a work moderately sophistic in general style and sentence-structure may be much later.

There is also a subtle quality about writings later than 300 B.C., an unnatural verbosity and tortuousness of expression, a suspicion of the "baboo," that is as unmistakable as it is impalpable. A few of the Hippocratic treatises display this characteristic.

(d) In some respects grammar and diction are the surest tests of all. If the negative μή is markedly ousting οὐ it is a sure sign of post-Alexandrine date. A preference for compound words with abstract meaning, in cases where a simple expression would easily have sufficed, is a mark of later Greek prose. If any reader wishes for concrete evidence to support my rather vague generalisations, he has only to read Epidemics I., then The Art or Regimen I., and finally Precepts or Decorum, and try to note the differences.